|
|
John Winthrop, in his 1644 document, Arbitrary Government Described,
found in the Harvard Classics (1910), Vol.43, p.98 - p.99, said:
Every law must be just in every part of it, but if the penalty annexed be unjust, how
can it be held forth as a just law? To prescribe a penalty must be by some rule, otherwise
it is an usurpation of God's prerogative; but where the law-makers, or declarers, cannot
find a rule for prescribing a penalty, if it come before the judges pro re nata,
there it is determinable by a certain rule, viz., by an ordinance set up of God for that
purpose, which hath a sure promise of Divine assistance (Exo. xxi. 22; Deut. xvi. 18).
"Judges and Officers shalt thou make, etc., and they shall judge the people with just
judgment." (Deut. xxv. 1, 2, and xvii. 9, 10, 11). [F]or a divine sentence is in the
lips of the King, his mouth transgresseth not in judgment (Prov. xvi.), but no such
promise was ever made to a paper sentence of human authority or invention. He who
hath promised His servants to teach them what to answer, even in that hour when they shall
be brought before judgment seats, etc., will also teach his ministers, the judges, what
sentence to pronounce, if they will also observe His word and trust in Him. "Care not
for the morrow, etc." is a rule of general extent, to all cases where our providence
may either cross with some rule or ordinance of His, or may occasion us to rely more upon
our own strengths and means, than upon His grace and blessing. In the sentence which
Solomon gave between the two harlots (1 Kings 111. 28), it is said that all Israel heard
of the judgment which the King had judged; and they feared the King, for they saw that the
wisdom of God was in him to do judgment. See here, how the wisdom of God was glorified,
and the authority of the judge strengthened by this sentence; whereas in men's prescript
sentences neither of these can be attained;
"Arbitrary government" comes when rulers ignore the law
of nature and of nature's God. A century later John Locke (falsely
charged in our day with deism) echoed this same
sentiment:
[T]he Law of Nature stands as an eternal rule to all men, legislators as well as
others. The rules that they make for other men's actions must . . . be conformable to the
Law of Nature, i.e., to the will of God. [L]aws human must be made according to the
general laws of Nature, and without contradiction to any positive law of Scripture,
otherwise they are ill made.
[Two Treatises on Government, Bk II sec 135. {quoting Hooker's Ecclesiastical
Polity {shows Puritan influence}]
And in this context, Madison placed our nation under the authority of God with his
proclamation:
Whereas the Congress of the United States, by a joint resolution of the two Houses,
have signified a request that a day may be recommended to be observed by the people of the
United States with religious solemnity as a day of public humiliation and prayer; and
Whereas such a recommendation will enable the several religious denominations and
societies so disposed to offer at one and the same time their common vows and adorations
to Almighty God on the solemn occasion produced by the war in which He has been pleased to
permit the injustice of a foreign power to involve these United States:
I do therefore recommend the third Thursday in August next as a convenient day to be set
apart for the devout purposes of rendering the Sovereign of the Universe and the
Benefactor of Mankind the public homage due to His holy attributes; of acknowledging the
transgressions which might justly provoke the manifestations of His divine displeasure; of
seeking His merciful forgiveness and His assistance in the great duties of repentance and
amendment, and especially of offering fervent supplications that in the present season of
calamity and war He would take the American people under His peculiar care and protection;
that He would guide their public councils, animate their patriotism, and bestow His
blessing on their arms; that He would inspire all nations with a love of justice and of
concord and with a reverence for the unerring precept of our holy religion to do to
others as they would require that others should do to them; and, finally, that, turning
the hearts of our enemies from the violence and injustice which sway their councils
against us, He would hasten a restoration of the blessings of peace. Given at Washington,
the 9th day of July, A. D. 1812. [SEAL.]
JAMES MADISON.
[From Annals of Congress, Twelfth Congress, part 2, 2224.]
BY THE PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA.
A PROCLAMATION.
Messages and Papers of the Presidents, James Madison, vol. 1, p.498
Pledged as we are, fellow-citizens, to these sacred engagements, we yet humbly,
fervently implore the Almighty Disposer of events to avert from our land war and
usurpation, the scourges of mankind; to permit our fields to be cultivated in peace; to
instil into nations the love of friendly intercourse; to suffer our youth to be educated
in virtue, and to preserve our morality from the pollution invariably incident to
habits of war; to prevent the laborer and husbandman from being harassed by taxes and
imposts; to remove from ambition the means of disturbing the commonwealth; to annihilate
all pretexts for power afforded by war; to maintain the Constitution; and to bless our
nation with tranquillity, under. whose benign influence we may reach the summit
of happiness and glory, to which we are destined by nature and
nature's God.
Virginia Resolutions of 1798, Pronouncing The Alien And Sedition Laws To Be
Unconstitutional, And Defining The Rights Of The States.
Drawn by Mr. Madison IN THE VIRGINIA HOUSE
OF DELEGATES Friday, December 21, 1798
Jonathan Elliot, Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution, Vol. 4,
p.532
[T]he rights essential to happiness . . . We claim them from a higher source -- from
the King of kings and Lord of all the earth
John Dickinson, Signer of Constitution, Governor of Pennsylvania,
The Political Writings of John Dickinson, (Wilmington: Bonsal and Niles, 1801) Vol.
1, p. 111.
The greatest engine of "tyranny" is a State which thinks it has
no responsibility to obey God. |
>Not everyone, either
>then or now, agrees with this radical secular principle, and they don't have
>to -- but it IS our standard of law, and it is what insures us against
>tyranny.
If it is our standard of law, why has the Court never said "this is a secular
nation," but the Court has in fact stated several times, This is a Christian nation?
Why is it none of the defining moments of American history were undertaken as atheists,
but in fact were engaged in as Christians?
The commander-in-chief directs that divine service be performed every Sunday at eleven
o'clock in those brigades [in] which there are chaplains; those which have none [are] to
attend the places of worship nearest to them. It is expected that officers of all ranks
will by their attendance set an example to their men. While we are zealously performing
the duties of good citizens and soldiers, we certainly ought not to be inattentive to the
higher duties of religion. To the distinguished character of patriot, it should be our
highest glory to add the more distinguished character of Christian. The signal
instances of providential goodness which we have experienced,
and which have now almost crowned our labors with complete success, demand from us in a
peculiar manner the warmest returns of gratitude and piety to the Supreme Author of all
good.
George Washington, General Orders. . (1778.)
The Writings of George Washington from the Original Manuscript Sources,
1745-1799. Edited by John C. Fitzpatrick. 39 vols. Washington: United States Government
Printing Office, 1931-44. vol. 11, p. 342.
The first difficulty to be overcome existed in Boston itself. Cushing, the speaker, who
had received a private letter from Dartmouth, and was lulled into confiding in "the
noble and generous sentiments" of that minister, advised that for the time the people
should bear their grievances. "Our natural increase in wealth and population,"
said he, "will in a course of years settle this dispute in our favor; whereas, if we
persist in denying the right of parliament to legislate for us, they may think us
extravagant in our demands, and there will be great danger of bringing on a rupture fatal
to both countries." He thought the redress of grievances would more surely come
"if these high points about the supreme authority of parliament were to fall
asleep." Against this feeble advice, the Boston committee of correspondence aimed at
the union of the province, and "the confederacy of the whole continent of
America." They refused to waive the claim of right, which could only divide the
Americans in sentiment and confuse their counsels. "What oppressions," they
asked, in their circular to all the other towns, "may we not expect in another seven
years, if through a weak credulity, while the most arbitrary measures are still persisted
in, we should be prevailed upon to submit our rights, as the patriotic Farmer expresses
it, to the tender mercies of the ministry? Watchfulness, unity, and harmony are necessary
to the salvation of ourselves and posterity from bondage. We have an animating
confidence in the Supreme Disposer of events, that he will never suffer a sensible, brave,
and virtuous people to be enslaved."
George Bancroft, History of the United States, Vol.3,
Chapter 34: The Boston Tea-Party, August-December 1773
p.443-44
The authority of Parliament was questioned only because of the
rights and absolutes given by the Creator.
In article <19990803143836.27185.00000367@ng-fl1.aol.com>, thr@aol.com (THR) writes:
>The basis for it is clearly revealed in the ferment of
>Enlightenment philosophers and scientists, and clearly reflected in the views
>of such
>reformers as Locke, Paine and Jefferson.
Paine was rejected by
the Founders because he rejected the authority of God:
Locke was a Christian. Quote Locke
for the proposition that America should not be under the authority of God. This is mere
name-dropping. Locke said (above) that our laws must be judged by the
Bible.
Locke does not deny the existence of God. . . . Rather, God has given individual human
beings powers of sensation and reflection, through which people can discover what they
need to know in this world. . . . . Locke was confident that a thorough intellectual
individualism, very reasonable, would secure mankind against the violence of Unreason.
Formal schooling, Locke thought, would suffice to keep human beings reasonable. In part,
Locke's theory of knowledge was a reaction against the religious fanaticism of
seventeenth-century Britain. Turn away from religious dogmatism, Locke is saying, in
effect: hereafter base your actions upon sweet reason, as ascertained by the individual's
five senses. But Locke did not foresee the coming, a century later, of fanatic political
ideology; still less did he foresee that there would develop a fanatic cult of Reason,
beginning in France.
Russell Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.291-92
This does not mean, however, that the Founding Fathers always
interpreted Lockean ideas in a purely Lockean manner. While they drew on the spirited
Locke of the Two Treatises on Government for practical purposes, there is little
evidence they accepted the relativistic and radical Locke of the Essay Concerning
Human Understanding. The Founders associated Locke with Richard Hooker and other
European (especially Protestant) natural law writers and the classical republican
tradition of England.
Matthew Spalding, "From Toleration to Liberty," Crisis Magazine,
July/August 1995, p.42
As for Jefferson,
This was true even of the more innovating Americans, among them
Thomas Jefferson. As Gilbert Chinard writes, "The Jeffersonian philosophy was born
under the sign of Hengist and Horsa, not of the Goddess Reason." That is, Jefferson
was more influenced by his understanding of English history (especially of the Anglo-Saxon
period, beginning with the landing in Britain of the Teutonic chieftains Hengist and
Horsa) than he was influenced by the rationalism of the Enlightenment. Jefferson knew his
Locke, and praised him highly; but in his Commonplace Book and his public papers,
Jefferson cited more frequently such juridical authorities as Coke and Kames. And
Jefferson denied that he had copied the Declaration of Independence from Locke's Second
Treatise.
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.291-92
Jefferson did not reject the authority of God in favor of the
authority of man or the authority of the federal government. The civil government was
to be "separate" from ecclesiastical governments, but BOTH were to be "under God." True religion secured civil prosperity.
The practice of morality being necessary for the well-being of society, He has
taken care to impress its precepts so indelibly on our hearts that they shall not be
effaced by the subtleties of our brain. We all agree in the obligation of the moral
precepts of Jesus, and nowhere will they be found delivered in greater purity than in his
discourses.
TJ to James Fishback, Sept 27, 1809, The Writings of Thomas Jefferson.
Edited by Albert Ellery Bergh. 20 vols. Washington: The Thomas Jefferson Memorial
Association, 1907, vol.12, p. 315.
Speaking of "the widespread denunciation of him by his political opponents as an
anti-Christian infidel or atheist," Foote observes,
[I]t is one of the minor ironies of history that such slanders should have been so
generally and so long believed about the man whose knowledge of and admiration for the
teachings of Jesus have never been equaled by any other President.
Henry Wilder Foote, "Introduction," The Jefferson Bible, 18
It was not, however, to be understood that instruction in religious opinion and duties
was meant to be precluded by the public authorities as indifferent to the interests of
society. On the contrary, the relations which exist between man and his Maker and the
duties resulting from those relations are the most interesting and important to every
human being and the most incumbent on his study and investigation. -- TJ, Report to the
Visitors [school boards] Oct 7, 1822
As between religion and irreligion, Jefferson did not hesitate to place the government
under the authority of God. Only the authority of Great Britain was challenged.
"In the summer of the year 1783, it was expected that the assembly of Virginia
would call a Convention for the establishment of a Constitution. The following draught of
a fundamental Constitution for the Commonwealth of Virginia was then prepared, with a
design of being proposed in such Convention had it taken place."
The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, Volume 2, p.281 Appendix No. II. Fundamental
Constitution for the Commonwealth of Virginia
To the citizens of the commonwealth of Virginia, and all others whom it may concern,
the delegates for the said commonwealth in Convention assembled, send greeting:
It is known to you and to the world, that the government of Great Britain, with which
the American States were not long since connected, assumed over them an authority
unwarrantable and oppressive; that they endeavored to enforce this authority by arms, and
that the States of New Hampshire, Massachusetts, Rhode Island, Connecticut, New York, New
Jersey, Pennsylvania, Delaware, Maryland, Virginia, North Carolina, South Carolina, and
Georgia, considering resistance, with all its train of horrors, as a lesser evil than
abject submission, closed in the appeal to arms. It hath pleased the Sovereign Disposer
of all human events to give to this appeal an issue favorable to the rights of the States;
to enable them to reject forever all dependence on a government which had shown itself
so capable of abusing the trusts reposed in it; and to obtain from that government a
solemn and explicit acknowledgment that they are free, sovereign, and independent States.
In article
<19990803143836.27185.00000367@ng-fl1.aol.com>, thr@aol.com (THR) writes: >The document, our Constitution,
>that upholds that standard of liberation, is as secular a document that could
>ever POSSIBLY be written for modeling a government. It was a quite conscious
>act of rebellion against authority.
If you want to see a secular society, go to France about the same time as the US
Constitution was being put into effect. Jefferson spoke of "The horrors of the French
revolution."[1] "Like the rest of mankind, he was disgusted with atrocities of
the French revolution. . . . " [2] "November the 5th, 1793. E. Randolph tells
me; that Hamilton, in conversation with him yesterday, said, "Sir, if all the people
in America were now assembled, and to call on me to say whether I am a friend to the
French revolution, I would declare that I have it in abhorrence." [3]
The leading feature in the mind and character of Thomas Jefferson was a firm and
undoubting belief in the worth and dignity of human nature, and in the capacity of man for
self government. . . . It seems to have been inborn; but whether inborn or communicated,
it ruled his life; it burst from him like the peal of an anthem when he came to pen the
immortal Declaration; his long residence in Europe only confirmed it; the excesses of
the French Revolution had no effect to abate it, and it breathes through every line of
his public utterances from his seat as President of the United States; it was the
foundation of his virtues and the source of his errors; and not only the source of these,
but the cause of the false imputation to him of errors he never committed; his friendships
and his enmities were alike due to it; he distrusted all who were not in full sympathy
with it, and they distrusted him.
. . .
The impulse of the movement which culminated in the French Revolution, reaching these
shores, stirred the sympathies and passions of both parties, the one espousing the cause
of Democratic France and the other of monarchical England. The Federal party, alarmed for
the public welfare, and fearful lest the license of the French revolutionists
should be repeated on this side of the water, sought to strengthen authority by those acts
of repressive Federal power, since generally condemned, called the Alien and Sedition
laws. [4]
It is probable, too, that by being boarded in a French family, the habit of speaking
that language may be obtained. I do not count on any advantage to be derived, in Geneva,
from a familiar acquaintance with the principles of that government. The late revolution
has rendered it a tyrannical aristocracy, more likely to give ill than good ideas to an
American.[5]
But [Jefferson] suffered bitter disappointment as he saw the [French Revolution]
degenerate into extremism and bloodshed after his departure from France. Years later, he
admitted that John Adams had been right in predicting that the revolution would fail to
produce a free republicbut even then he was not willing to give up hope for the
future:
Your prophecies [about the French Revolution] proved truer than mine.
The
destruction of eight or ten millions of human beings has probably been the effect of these
convulsions. I did not, in 1789, believe they would have lasted so long, nor have cost so
much blood.
But although your prophecy has proved true so far, I hope it does not preclude a better
final result. 22 [TJ to John Adams (11 Jan. 1816), Bergh 14:395-96. See also TJ to John
Adams (28 Oct. 1813), Bergh 13:402. [6]
1. The Anas. The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, Volume 1, p.281-82.
2. Ibid, p. 282-83
3. The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, Volume 1, p.402, Cabinet Meetings.
4. "The University of Virginia, and Thomas Jefferson, Its Father," An Address
delivered by James C. Carter, LL. D., upon the occasion of the Dedication of the new
Buildings of the University, June 14, 1898. The Writings of Thomas Jefferson,
Volume 2, p.viiviii, xxx-xxxi
5. Letter to J. Bannister, Junior PARIS, October 15, 1785. The Writings of Thomas
Jefferson, Volume 5, p.185188
6. Allison, The Real Thomas Jefferson, p.147 |
During the French Revolution, the great French chemist Lavoisier was put on trial, and
chalked on the wall just above his head was the slogan "The Republic has no use
for scientists." He was guillotined.
Richard Nixon, "Remarks on Presenting the National Medal of Science Awards for
1970," May 21, 1971, Public Papers of the Presidents, Nixon, 1971, No. 176,
p.650.
Nor is the American Revolution conceivable without the religious background. The
difference between the American Revolution and the French Revolution is that the American
Revolution, in its origins, was a religious event, whereas the French Revolution was an
antireligious event. As John Adams was to put it long afterward, in 1818: "The
Revolution was effected before the war commenced. The Revolution was in the minds and
hearts of the people: and change in their religious sentiments of their duties and
obligations."
Paul Johnson, "God and the Americans," §1. The City Upon a Hill, The American
Jewish Committee, Commentary Magazine, January 1995, p.31
Russell Kirk describes the differences between the two Revolutions (and note that he is
not a Theocrat, and describes the Constitution as "secular," but as resting on
the authority of God):
A principal difference between the American Revolution and the French Revolution was
this: the American revolutionaries in general held a biblical view of man and his bent
toward sin, while the French revolutionaries in general attempted to substitute for the
biblical understanding an optimistic doctrine of human goodness advanced by the
philosophes of the rationalistic Enlightenment. The American view led to the Constitution
of 1787; the French view, to the Terror and to a new autocracy. The American Constitution
is a practical secular covenant, drawn up by men who (with few exceptions) believed in a
sacred Covenant, designed to restrain the human tendencies toward violence and fraud; the
American Constitution is a fundamental law deliberately meant to place checks upon will
and appetite. The French innovators would endure no such checks upon popular impulses;
they ended under a far more arbitrary domination.
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.29
When the American Revolution came, it would not be a revolution
against a church by law established, or against Christian teachingin this very
unlike the French Revolution. In America, Browne was read only by the well educated; his
Anglican learning and his Christian aphorisms reached the mass of people only slowly and
indirectly. A large proportion of the leading classes in America were Anglican,
nevertheless, and the Christianity of gentlemen like George Washington was very like the
Christianity of Sir Thomas Browne.
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.277
In article <19990803143836.27185.00000367@ng-fl1.aol.com>,
thr@aol.com (THR) writes:
>The basis for it is clearly revealed in the ferment of
>Enlightenment philosophers and scientists, and clearly reflected in the views
>of such
>reformers as Locke, Paine and Jefferson.
As we have seen,
As for the Enlightenment, Russell Kirk shows that the
Enlightenment and the ideas of the French Revolution were not as influential in America as
secular myth-makers would have us believe.
At the heart of the "Enlightenment" mentality was an
enormous confidence in the reason of the individual human being. Man's private
intellectual faculties, if awakened, could suffice to dissolve all mysteries and solve all
problemsso the Encyclopedists believed. Religion must be discarded as mere
superstition, old political forms must be swept away as irrational and oppressive, the
natural goodness of man must be enabled to prevailthrough an appeal to Reason. If
properly cultivated, every man's private rationality could emancipate him from the
delusion of sin, from ways of violence and fraud, from confusion and fear. This dream
ended in the French Revolution.
To America, the mentality of the Enlightenment scarcely
penetrated. A few Americans of cosmopolitan experience, notably Benjamin Franklin, were
affected by these doctrinesbut even in them, the boundless optimism of the typical
philosophe was chastened by direct experience of reality in practical America. A moderate
Deism was the furthest advance of Enlightenment theories in the Thirteen Colonies. The
eighteenth-century men of ideas whose direct influence upon Americans was strongest stood
in partial or total opposition to the philosophes generally and the Encyclopedists
particularly. Montesquieu, with his devotion to the hard lessons of historical knowledge;
Hume, with his good-natured contempt for the cult of Reason; Blackstone, governed by legal
precedent and prescription; Burke, appealing to the great traditions of medieval and
Christian and classical beliefthese were America's teachers in the latter half of
the eighteenth century. If they enlightened, it was not with the torch of the French
Enlightenment.
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.349
At the Constitutional Convention in 1787, no man would be more
frequently cited and quoted than Charles Louis de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu
(16891755). . . . All of Montesquieu's writings were eagerly read, in youth, by many
of the men who signed the Declaration of Independence and drew up the Constitution of the
United States; others absorbed Montesquieu's ideas at second hand through Blackstone's Commentaries
on the Laws of England.
Montesquieu's ascendancy over English and American minds was not
gained because he was a radical innovator: he was nothing of that sort. On the contrary,
Montesquieu expressed better than could any Englishman or American of his day the very
principles in which most thinking Englishmen and Americans already believed. He had
resided for two years in England, and was an ardent admirer of the English constitution.
His understanding of the nature of law confirmed Englishmen and Americans in their
affection for their own jurisprudence and legal institutions; his discussion of the power
of custom and habit in shaping society agreed with the prescriptive politics of the
English-speaking peoples; his advocacy of the separation of powers sustained the political
experience of Britain and the colonies. Upon Englishmen and Americans, his influence was
conservative.
It would be somewhat otherwise in France, where
Montesquieu's praise of the English constitution would produce demands for reconstruction
of the French political structure upon the English model. Those who so read Montesquieu
were disappointed in the event. For as Montesquieu himself made clear, one country's
historic experience cannot be transported to a different land, and customs and habits
cannot be altered by positive lawthey can only be distorted. In France, the early
ideals of many revolutionaries, Mirabeau among them, were connected with the English
pattern of politics. But the Revolution, as it ran its course, redoubled the very
defectscentralization especiallywhich Montesquieu had assailed obliquely in
the France of the Old Regime; what emerged from the French Revolution did not resemble
either the English constitution or Montesquieu's general model of a constitution with
separation of powers and local liberties. Somewhat wistfully, Montesquieu had desired
French reformbut no revolution. In America, his great book would help in the
recovery of order after a revolution.
Although Montesquieu was a witty critic of the Church in his age, at bottom his
understanding of natural law is religious.
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.350-53
This has been only a summary description of the temperate wisdom
of Montesquieu. Because his principles of politics found their best embodiment in
eighteenth-century England, his reputation in that realm stood high. And it is not
difficult to understand why Montesquieu was far more popular with Americans than he was
either with the French masters of the Old Regime or with the rash French reformers who
brought on the Revolution.
For Montesquieu's understanding of the nature of law was
shared by the Americans. They recognized religious and moral sanctions behind positive
law; they had been brought up in the English juridical principles and practices of common
law and equity, which clearly had developed out of a people's experience in community;
they looked upon law as the protector of freedom. The Americans knew that their own
society was not the product of a single formal social compact; it was in part an
inheritance from British social development, and in part the consequence of their own
peculiar geographical, economic, and political circumstances; it had grown accidentally or
providentially, rather than being created out of an abstract general agreement. They
understood very well indeed the benefits of separation of powers and of checks and
balances: in every colony, the governor held executive power, the assembly representing
the freeholders controlled legislation, and the courts were independent. (In Virginia, the
county courts even resembled Montesquieu's "depository of laws.")
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.356-7
In this, the American Revolution differed vastly from the French
Revolution. The Americans, in essence, meant to keep their old order and defend it against
external interference; but [p.396] the French rising was what Edmund Burke called "a
revolution of theoretic dogma," intended to bring down the Old Regime and substitute
something quite new. (Just what that something new might be, the French revolutionary
factions disputed violently among themselves.)
Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.395-96
"Happy, thrice
happy the people of America! whose gentleness of manners and habits of virtue are still
sufficient to reconcile the enjoyment of their natural rights, with the peace and
tranquillity of their country; whose principles of religious liberty did not result from
an indiscriminate contempt of all religion whatever, and whose equal representation in
their legislative councils was founded upon an equality really existing among them, and
not upon the metaphysical speculations of fanciful politicians, vainly contending against
the unalterable course of events, and the established order of nature."
John Quincy Adams to Friedrich Gentz, June 16, 1800, and his
"Letters of Publicola", June-July, 1791, in Writings of John Quincy Adams
(edited by Worthington Chauncy Ford; New York: Macmillan, 1913), Vol. II, p. 463, and Vol.
I, p. 98. Cited in Kirk, The Roots of American Order, p.397
Later in the nineteenth century, the talented French writers
Alexis de Tocqueville and Hippolyte Taine would judge the French Revolution similarly. In
the twentieth century, American historians tend to confirm Gentz's verdict. "The
Americans of 1776," Clinton Rossiter writes, "were among the first men in modern
history to defend rather than to seek an open society and constitutional liberty; their
political faith, like the appeal to arms it supported, was therefore surprisingly
sober...Perhaps the most remarkable characteristic of this political theory was its
deep-seated conservatism. However radical the principles of the Revolution may have seemed
to the rest of the world, in the minds of the colonists they were thoroughly preservative
and respectful of the past...The political theory of the American Revolution, in contrast
to that of the French Revolution, was not a theory designed to make the world over."
Clinton Rossiter, Seedtime of the Republic: the Origin of the American Tradition of
Political Liberty (New York: Harcourt, Brace 1953), p. 448. Kirk, The Roots of
American Order, p.399
As Gentz points out, there occurred persecutions, cruelties,
confiscations, and exiling of honest people in the course of the American Revolution also.
"But what are all these single instances of injustice and oppression, compared with
the universal flood of misery and ruin, which the French revolution let loose upon France,
and all the neighboring countries? If, even in America, private hatred, or local
circumstances, threatened property or personal security; if here and there even the public
authorities became the instruments of injustice, of revenge, and of a persecuting spirit,
yet did the poison never flow into every vein of the social body; never, as in France, was
the contempt of all rights, and of the very simplest precepts of humanity, made the
general maxim of legislation, and the unqualified prescription of systematic
tyranny."
Friedrich Gentz, The French and American Revolutions
Compared (edited by Russell Kirk; Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1955), pp. 44, 60, 81. Kirk,
The Roots of American Order, p.399
But "rights," like freedom itself, can prove
illusory. Many of those who drew up that first declaration of rights in 1789 were
slaughtered in the terror four years later, or imprisoned, or killed in the Bonapartist
tyranny which eventually took its place time and again. The revolutionary Saturn devours
its children, as the French Revolution, the Russian Revolution, and the Chinese Revolution
have demonstrated with horrific plentitude. During the 20th century something like 100
million men, women, and children have been put to death by regimes nominally devoted to
liberty and human rights. The process continues. In theory, no people enjoy more rights,
greater liberty, or the chance of higher prosperity, than the 1000 million people who live
under the constitution of the People's Republic of China. But the constitution is not
worth the paper it is printed on. In practice, no people on earth have a stronger chance
of ending up inside a concentration or labor camp. About 20 million are in the Chinese
Gulag at this very time. Most of them are slave-laborers. Few, even if they serve fixed
sentences, are ever again likely to enjoy even the limited freedoms which uncriminalized
Chinese possess. The rule of law means nothing in Communist China. So the right to vote is
meaningless and the ordinary Chinese, while theoretically enjoying independence, are in
reality less free than during the colonial period when large enclaves of the country were
run by Europeans and North Americans.
Paul Johnson, "Freedom: Taking Account of Human
Nature,"
The Morley Institute, Crisis Magazine, March 1995, p.22
>The document, our Constitution,
>that upholds that standard of liberation, is as secular a document that could
>ever POSSIBLY be written for modeling a government. It was a quite conscious
>act of rebellion against authority.
As I have attempted to show, this statement represents a fundamental
misunderstanding of American history. America's break with Britain was
conservative, not revolutionary, and based on religious motivations, not a desire to
secularize America's religious history. The concept of arbitrary authority is a Christian
concept, and the "historical context" for resistance to arbitrary authority,
which THR says I have robbed, goes back to the Puritans, not the Enlightenment. |